Western philosophy - Analytic, Continental, Existentialism | Britannica
Table of Contents
References & Edit History Related Topics

Contemporary philosophy

Despite the tradition of philosophical professionalism established during the Enlightenment by Wolff and Kant, philosophy in the 19th century was still created largely outside the universities. Comte, Mill, Marx, Kierkegaard, and Schopenhauer were not professors, and only the German idealist school was rooted in academic life. Since the mid-20th century, however, most well-known philosophers have been associated with academia. Philosophers more and more employ a technical vocabulary and deal with specialized problems, and they write not for a broad intellectual public but for one another. Professionalism also has sharpened the divisions between philosophical schools and made the questions of what philosophy is and what it ought to be matters of the sharpest controversy. Philosophy has become extremely self-conscious about its own method and nature.

The most-significant divisions in 20th-century philosophy were influenced and intensified by geographic and cultural differences. The tradition of clear logical analysis, inaugurated by Locke and Hume, dominated the English-speaking world, whereas a speculative and broadly historical tradition, begun by Hegel but later diverging radically from him, held sway on the European continent. From the early decades of the century, the substantive as well as stylistic differences between the two approaches—known after World War II as analytic and Continental philosophy, respectively—gradually became more pronounced, and until the 1990s few serious attempts were made to find common ground between them.

Other significant currents in 20th-century philosophy were the speculative philosophies of Henri Bergson (1859–1941) of France, John Dewey (1859–1952) of the United States, and Alfred North Whitehead (1861–1947) of England—each of whom evades easy classification—and the philosophical Marxism practiced from the early 20th century in parts of central Europe and the West, later including the United States and Latin America.

Bergson, Dewey, and Whitehead

In his An Introduction to Metaphysics (1903) and in his masterpiece, Creative Evolution (1907), Bergson distinguished between two profoundly different ways of knowing: the method of analysis, which is characteristic of science, and the method of intuition, a kind of intellectual sympathy through which it is possible to enter into objects and other persons and identify with them. All basic metaphysical truths, Bergson held, are grasped by philosophical intuition. This is how one comes to know one’s deepest self and the essence of all living things, which he called “duration,” as well as the “vital spirit,” which is the mysterious creative agency in the world.

For Whitehead, philosophy is primarily metaphysics, or “speculative philosophy,” which he described as the effort “to frame a coherent, logical, necessary system of general ideas in terms of which every element of our experience can be interpreted.” Whitehead’s philosophy was thus an attempt to survey the world with a large generality of understanding, an end toward which his great trilogy—Science and the Modern World (1925), Process and Reality (1929), and Adventures of Ideas (1933)—was directed.

Whereas Bergson and Whitehead were principally metaphysicians and philosophers of culture, Dewey was a generalist who stressed the unity, interrelationship, and organicity of all forms of philosophical knowledge. He is chiefly notable for the fact that his conception of philosophy stressed so powerfully the notions of practicality and moral purpose. One of the guiding aims of Dewey’s philosophizing was the effort to find the same warranted assertibility for ethical and political judgments as for scientific ones. Philosophy, he said, should be oriented not to professional pride but to human need.

Dewey’s approach to the social problems of the 20th century, unlike that of Vladimir Lenin (1870–1924), emphasized not revolution but the continuous application of the intellect to social affairs. He believed in social planning—in conscious intelligent intervention to produce desirable social change—and he proposed a new “experimentalism” as a guide to enlightened public action to promote the aims of a democratic community. His pragmatic social theory is the first major political philosophy produced by modern liberal democracy.