R$ 47,97
Entrega GRÁTIS: 28 - 29 de Maio no seu primeiro pedido
Em estoque
R$ R$ 47,97 () Inclui opções selecionadas. Inclui parcela mensal inicial e opções selecionadas. Detalhes
Preço
Subtotal
R$ R$ 47,97
Subtotal
Detalhamento do pagamento inicial
Custo do frete, data de entrega e total do pedido (incluindo impostos) mostrados na finalização da compra.
Enviado por
Amazon.com.br
Enviado por
Amazon.com.br
Vendido por
Amazon.com.br
Vendido por
Amazon.com.br
Devolução
Elegível para Devolução, Reembolso ou Troca em até 30 dias após o recebimento
Elegível para Devolução, Reembolso ou Troca em até 30 dias após o recebimento
Este item pode ser devolvido em sua condição original para um reembolso total ou troca em até 30 dias após o recebimento.
Devolução
Elegível para Devolução, Reembolso ou Troca em até 30 dias após o recebimento
Este item pode ser devolvido em sua condição original para um reembolso total ou troca em até 30 dias após o recebimento.
Pagamento
Transação segura
Sua compra é segura
Trabalhamos constantemente para proteger a sua segurança e privacidade. Nosso sistema de segurança de pagamento criptografa suas informações durante a compra. Não compartilhamos os detalhes do seu cartão de crédito com vendedores parceiros e não vendemos suas informações. Saiba mais
Pagamento
Transação segura
Trabalhamos constantemente para proteger a sua segurança e privacidade. Nosso sistema de segurança de pagamento criptografa suas informações durante a compra. Não compartilhamos os detalhes do seu cartão de crédito com vendedores parceiros e não vendemos suas informações. Saiba mais
Imagem do logotipo do app Kindle

Baixe o app Kindle gratuito e comece a ler livros do Kindle instantaneamente em seu smartphone, tablet ou computador - sem a necessidade de um dispositivo Kindle.

Leia instantaneamente em seu navegador com o Kindle para internet.

Usando a câmera do seu celular, digitalize o código abaixo e baixe o app Kindle.

Código QR para baixar o aplicativo Kindle

Algo deu errado. Tente fazer sua solicitação novamente mais tarde.

Synchronicity: An Acausal Connecting Principle: An Acausal Connecting Principle. (from Vol. 8. of the Collected Works of C. G. Jung): 08 Capa comum – 14 novembro 2010

4,6 4,6 de 5 estrelas 1.015 avaliações de clientes

{"desktop_buybox_group_1":[{"displayPrice":"R$ 47,97","priceAmount":47.97,"currencySymbol":"R$","integerValue":"47","decimalSeparator":",","fractionalValue":"97","symbolPosition":"left","hasSpace":true,"showFractionalPartIfEmpty":true,"offerListingId":"0hcQJOAWbj%2FxY%2B9e3CGhjP480PZjsYVz7gpXsjBGf1lokaDmNaQTU%2F06M0m%2BMXA2Kuxc09kV5reWWB5VQcFpzs5cgnnGJA35%2Fab2fFfHXW8FWSRKkxWKEpv7FfwnAhOt5Mv3bxhXcUOU7etuNGr9lB1FZ7KkDmd6","locale":"pt-BR","buyingOptionType":"NEW","aapiBuyingOptionIndex":0}]}

Opções de compra e produtos complementares

Jung was intrigued from early in his career with coincidences, especially those surprising juxtapositions that scientific rationality could not adequately explain. He discussed these ideas with Albert Einstein before World War I, but first used the term "synchronicity" in a 1930 lecture, in reference to the unusual psychological insights generated from consulting the I Ching. A long correspondence and friendship with the Nobel Prize-winning physicist Wolfgang Pauli stimulated a final, mature statement of Jung's thinking on synchronicity, originally published in 1952 and reproduced here. Together with a wealth of historical and contemporary material, this essay describes an astrological experiment Jung conducted to test his theory. Synchronicity reveals the full extent of Jung's research into a wide range of psychic phenomena.

This paperback edition of Jung's classic work includes a new foreword by Sonu Shamdasani, Philemon Professor of Jung History at University College London.

Leia mais Leia menos

Frequentemente comprados juntos

R$47,97
Em estoque
Enviado de e vendido por Amazon.com.br.
+
R$50,98
Em estoque
Enviado de e vendido por Amazon.com.br.
+
R$54,57
Enviado de e vendido por Amazon.com.br.
Preço total:
Para ver nosso preço, adicione este item ao seu carrinho.
Detalhes
Adicionado ao carrinho
spCSRF_Control
Alguns destes itens são enviados mais rapidamente que os outros.
Escolha itens para compra conjunta.

Descrição do produto

Sobre o Autor

Sonu Shamdasani is editor of The Red Book and Philemon Professor of Jung History at University College London.

Trecho. © Reimpressão autorizada. Todos os direitos reservados

SYNCHRONICITY

An Acausal Connecting PrincipleBy C. G. Jung

PRINCETON UNIVERSITY PRESS

Copyright © 2011 SONU SHAMDASANI
All right reserved.

ISBN: 978-0-691-15050-5

Contents

FOREWORD TO THE 2010 EDITION....................................viiEDITORIAL PREFACE...............................................xiFOREWORD........................................................31. Exposition...................................................52. An Astrological Experiment...................................433. Forerunners of the Idea of Synchronicity.....................694. Conclusion...................................................89APPENDIX: On Synchronicity......................................104BIBLIOGRAPHY....................................................117INDEX...........................................................125

Chapter One

EXPOSITION

818 The discoveries of modern physics have, as we know, brought about a significant change in our scientific picture of the world, in that they have shattered the absolute validity of natural law and made it relative. Natural laws are statistical truths, which means that they are completely valid only when we are dealing with macrophysical quantities. In the realm of very small quantities prediction becomes uncertain, if not impossible, because very small quantities no longer behave in accordance with the known natural laws.

819 The philosophical principle that underlies our conception of natural law is causality. But if the connection between cause and effect turns out to be only statistically valid and only relatively true, then the causal principle is only of relative use for explaining natural processes and therefore presupposes the existence of one or more other factors which would be necessary for an explanation. This is as much as to say that the connection of events may in certain circumstances be other than causal, and requires another principle of explanation.

820 We shall naturally look round in vain in the macrophysical world for acausal events, for the simple reason that we cannot imagine events that are connected non-causally and are capable of a non-causal explanation. But that does not mean that such events do not exist. Their existence—or at least their possibility —follows logically from the premise of statistical truth.

821 The experimental method of inquiry aims at establishing regular events which can be repeated. Consequently, unique or rare events are ruled out of account. Moreover, the experiment imposes limiting conditions on nature, for its aim is to force her to give answers to questions devised by man. Every answer of nature is therefore more or less influenced by the kind of questions asked, and the result is always a hybrid product. The so-called "scientific view of the world" based on this can hardly be anything more than a psychologically biased partial view which misses out all those by no means unimportant aspects that cannot be grasped statistically. But, to grasp these unique or rare events at all, we seem to be dependent on equally "unique" and individual descriptions. This would result in a chaotic collection of curiosities, rather like those old natural history cabinets where one finds, cheek by jowl with fossils and anatomical monsters in bottles, the horn of a unicorn, a mandragora manikin, and a dried mermaid. The descriptive sciences, and above all biology in the widest sense, are familiar with these "unique" specimens, and in their case only one example of an organism, no matter how unbelievable it may be, is needed to establish its existence. At any rate numerous observers will be able to convince themselves, on the evidence of their own eyes, that such a creature does in fact exist. But where we are dealing with ephemeral events which leave no demonstrable traces behind them except fragmentary memories in people's minds, then a single witness no longer suffices, nor would several witnesses be enough to make a unique event appear absolutely credible. One has only to think of the notorious unreliability of eye-witness accounts. In these circumstances we are faced with the necessity of finding out whether the apparently unique event is really unique in our recorded experience, or whether the same or similar events are not to be found elsewhere. Here the consensus omnium plays a very important role psychologically, though empirically it is somewhat doubtful, for only in exceptional cases does the consensus omnium prove to be of value in establishing facts. The empiricist will not leave it out of account, but will do better not to rely on it. Absolutely unique and ephemeral events whose existence we have no means of either denying or proving can never be the object of empirical science; rare events might very well be, provided that there was a sufficient number of reliable individual observations. The so-called possibility of such events is of no importance whatever, for the criterion of what is possible in any age is derived from that age's rationalistic assumptions. There are no "absolute" natural laws to whose authority one can appeal in support of one's prejudices. The most that can fairly be demanded is that the number of individual observations shall be as high as possible. If this number, statistically considered, falls within the limits of chance expectation, then it has been statistically proved that it was a question of chance; but no explanation has thereby been furnished. There has merely been an exception to the rule. When, for instance, the number of symptoms indicating a complex falls below the probable number of disturbances to be expected during the association experiment, this is no justification for assuming that no complex exists. But that did not prevent the reaction disturbances from being regarded earlier as pure chance.

822 Although, in biology especially, we move in a sphere where causal explanations often seem very unsatisfactory—indeed, well-nigh impossible—we shall not concern ourselves here with the problems of biology, but rather with the question whether there may not be some general field where acausal events not only are possible but are found to be actual facts.

823 Now, there is in our experience an immeasurably wide field whose extent forms, as it were, the counterbalance to the domain of causality. This is the world of chance, where a chance event seems causally unconnected with the coinciding fact. So we shall have to examine the nature and the whole idea of chance a little more closely. Chance, we say, must obviously be susceptible of some causal explanation and is only called "chance" or "coincidence" because its causality has not yet been discovered. Since we have an inveterate conviction of the absolute validity of causal law, we regard this explanation of chance as being quite adequate. But if the causal principle is only relatively valid, then it follows that even though in the vast majority of cases an apparently chance series can be causally explained, there must still remain a number of cases which do not show any causal connection. We are therefore faced with the task of sifting chance events and separating the acausal ones from those that can be causally explained. It stands to reason that the number of causally explicable events will far exceed those suspected of acausality, for which reason a superficial or prejudiced observer may easily overlook the relatively rare acausal phenomena. As soon as we come to deal with the problem of chance the need for a statistical evaluation of the events in question forces itself upon us.

824 It is not possible to sift the empirical material without a criterion of distinction. How are we to recognize acausal combinations of events, since it is obviously impossible to examine all chance happenings for their causality? The answer to this is that acausal events may be expected most readily where, on closer reflection, a causal connection appears to be inconceivable. As an example I would cite the "duplication of cases" which is a phenomenon well known to every doctor. Occasionally there is a trebling or even more, so that Kammerer can speak of a "law of series," of which he gives a number of excellent examples. In the majority of such cases there is not even the remotest probability of a causal connection between the coinciding events. When for instance I am faced with the fact that my tram ticket bears the same number as the theatre ticket which I buy immediately afterwards, and I receive that same evening a telephone call during which the same number is mentioned again as a telephone number, then a causal connection between these events seems to me improbable in the extreme, although it is obvious that each must have its own causality. I know, on the other hand, that chance happenings have a tendency to fall into aperiodic groupings—necessarily so, because otherwise there would be only a periodic or regular arrangement of events which would by definition exclude chance.

825 Kammerer holds that though "runs" or successions of chance events are not subject to the operation of a common cause, i.e., are acausal, they are nevertheless an expression of inertia—the property of persistence. The simultaneity of a "run of the same thing side by side" he explains as "imitation." Here he contradicts himself, for the run of chance has not been "removed outside the realm of the explicable," but, as we would expect, is included within it and is consequently reducible, if not to a common cause, then at least to several causes. His concepts of seriality, imitation, attraction, and inertia belong to a causally conceived view of the world and tell us no more than that the run of chance corresponds to statistical and mathematical probability. Kammerer's factual material contains nothing but runs of chance whose only "law" is probability; in other words, there is no apparent reason why he should look behind them for anything else. But for some obscure reason he does look behind them for something more than mere probability warrants—for a law of seriality which he would like to introduce as a principle coexistent with causality and finality. This tendency, as I have said, is in no way justified by his material. I can only explain this obvious contradiction by supposing that he had a dim but fascinated intuition of an acausal arrangement and combination of events, probably because, like all thoughtful and sensitive natures, he could not escape the peculiar impression which runs of chance usually make on us, and therefore, in accordance with his scientific disposition, took the bold step of postulating an acausal seriality on the basis of empirical material that lay within the limits of probability. Unfortunately he did not attempt a quantitative evaluation of seriality. Such an undertaking would undoubtedly have thrown up questions that are difficult to answer. The investigation of individual cases serves well enough for the purpose of general orientation, but only quantitative evaluation or the statistical method promises results in dealing with chance.

826 Chance groupings or series seem, at least to our present way of thinking, to be meaningless, and to fall as a general rule within the limits of probability. There are, however, incidents whose "chancefulness" seems open to doubt. To mention but one example out of many, I noted the following on April 1, 1949: Today is Friday. We have fish for lunch. Somebody happens to mention the custom of making an "April fish" of someone. That same morning I made a note of an inscription which read: "Est homo totus medius piscis ab imo." In the afternoon a former patient of mine, whom I had not seen for months, showed me some extremely impressive pictures of fish which she had painted in the meantime. In the evening I was shown a piece of embroidery with fish-like sea-monsters in it. On the morning of April 2 another patient, whom I had not seen for many years, told me a dream in which she stood on the shore of a lake and saw a large fish that swam straight towards her and landed at her feet. I was at this time engaged on a study of the fish symbol in history. Only one of the persons mentioned here knew anything about it.

827 The suspicion that this must be a case of meaningful coincidence, i.e., an acausal connection, is very natural. I must own that this run of events made a considerable impression on me. It seemed to me to have a certain numinous quality. In such circumstances we are inclined to say, "That cannot be mere chance," without knowing what exactly we are saying. Kammerer would no doubt have reminded me of his "seriality." The strength of an impression, however, proves nothing against the fortuitous coincidence of all these fishes. It is, admittedly, exceedingly odd that the fish theme recurs no less than six times within twenty-four hours. But one must remember that fish on Friday is the usual thing, and on April i one might very easily think of the April fish. I had at that time been working on the fish symbol for several months. Fishes frequently occur as symbols of unconscious contents. So there is no possible justification for seeing in this anything but a chance grouping. Runs or series which are composed of quite ordinary occurrences must for the present be regarded as fortuitous. However wide their range may be, they must be ruled out as acausal connections. It is, therefore, generally assumed that all coincidences are lucky hits and do not require an acausal interpretation. This assumption can, and indeed must, be regarded as true so long as proof is lacking that their incidence exceeds the limits of probability. Should this proof be forthcoming, however, it would prove at the same time that there are genuinely non-causal combinations of events for whose explanation we should have to postulate a factor incommensurable with causality. We should then have to assume that events in general are related to one another on the one hand as causal chains, and on the other hand by a kind of meaningful cross-connection.

828 Here I should like to draw attention to a treatise of Schopenhauer's, "On the Apparent Design in the Fate of the Individual," 13 which originally stood godfather to the views I am now developing. It deals with the "simultaneity of the causally unconnected, which we call 'chance'." Schopenhauer illustrates this simultaneity by a geographical analogy, where the parallels represent the cross-connection between the meridians, which are thought of as causal chains.

All the events in a man's life would accordingly stand in two fundamentally different kinds of connection: firstly, in the objective, causal connection of the natural process; secondly, in a subjective connection which exists only in relation to the individual who experiences it, and which is thus as subjective as his own dreams. ... That both kinds of connection exist simultaneously, and the selfsame event, although a link in two totally different chains, nevertheless falls into place in both, so that the fate of one individual invariably fits the fate of the other, and each is the hero of his own drama while simultaneously figuring in a drama foreign to him—this is something that surpasses our powers of comprehension, and can only be conceived as possible by virtue of the most wonderful pre-established harmony.

In his view "the subject of the great dream of life ... is but one," the transcendental Will, the prima causa, from which all causal chains radiate like meridian lines from the poles and, because of the circular parallels, stand to one another in a meaningful relationship of simultaneity. Schopenhauer believed in the absolute determinism of the natural process and furthermore in a first cause. There is nothing to warrant either assumption. The first cause is a philosophical mythologem which is only credible when it appears in the form of the old paradox [TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII.], as unity and multiplicity at once. The idea that the simultaneous points in the causal chains, or meridians, represent meaningful coincidences would only hold water if the first cause really were a unity. But if it were a multiplicity, which is just as likely, then Schopenhauer's whole explanation collapses, quite apart from the fact, which we have only recently realized, that natural law possesses a merely statistical validity and thus keeps the door open to indeterminism. Neither philosophical reflection nor experience can provide any evidence for the regular occurrence of these two kinds of connection, in which the same thing is both subject and object. Schopenhauer thought and wrote at a time when causality held sovereign sway as a category a priori and had therefore to be dragged in to explain meaningful coincidences. But, as we have seen, it can do this with some degree of probability only if we have recourse to the other, equally arbitrary assumption of the unity of the first cause. It then follows as a necessity that every point on a given meridian stands in a relationship of meaningful coincidence to every other point on the same degree of latitude. This conclusion, however, goes far beyond the bounds of what is empirically possible, for it credits meaningful coincidences with occurring so regularly and systematically that their verification would be either unnecessary or the simplest thing in the world. Schopenhauer's examples carry as much or as little conviction as all the others. Nevertheless, it is to his credit that he saw the problem and understood that there are no facile ad hoc explanations. Since this problem is concerned with the foundations of our epistemology, he derived it in accordance with the general trend of his philosophy from a transcendental premise, from the Will which creates life and being on all levels, and which modulates each of these levels in such a way that they are not only in harmony with their synchronous parallels but also prepare and arrange future events in the form of Fate or Providence.

(Continues...)


Excerpted from SYNCHRONICITYby C. G. Jung Copyright © 2011 by SONU SHAMDASANI. Excerpted by permission of PRINCETON UNIVERSITY PRESS. All rights reserved. No part of this excerpt may be reproduced or reprinted without permission in writing from the publisher.
Excerpts are provided by Dial-A-Book Inc. solely for the personal use of visitors to this web site.

Detalhes do produto

  • Editora ‏ : ‎ Princeton University Press; Revised ed. edição (14 novembro 2010)
  • Idioma ‏ : ‎ Inglês
  • Capa comum ‏ : ‎ 135 páginas
  • ISBN-10 ‏ : ‎ 0691150508
  • ISBN-13 ‏ : ‎ 978-0691150505
  • Dimensões ‏ : ‎ 13.34 x 1.27 x 20.96 cm
  • Avaliações dos clientes:
    4,6 4,6 de 5 estrelas 1.015 avaliações de clientes

Sobre o autor

Siga autores para obter atualizações de novos lançamentos e recomendações aprimoradas.
Carl Gustav Jung
Brief content visible, double tap to read full content.
Full content visible, double tap to read brief content.

Descubra mais livros do autor, veja autores semelhantes, leia blogs de autores e muito mais

Avaliações de clientes

4,6 de 5 estrelas
4,6 de 5
1.015 avaliações globais

Principal avaliação do Brasil

Avaliado no Brasil em 22 de agosto de 2023
Edição monótona, enfadonha, cansativa. Trata-se de mera impressão de texto, sem tratamento gráfico.
Não tem coerência com a obra de Jung, geralmente bem diagramada e ilustrada. A espera também foi bem maior do que o previsto, e eu deveria ter cancelado. Não recomendo.
1 pessoa achou isso útil
Denunciar

Principais avaliações de outros países

Traduzir todas as avaliações para português
Lea Johnson
5,0 de 5 estrelas Meaningful coincidences
Avaliado no Canadá em 4 de setembro de 2021
Brilliant mind! Very powerful: the reality of meaningful coincidences and the impact on one's life.🕺💃
AAA
4,0 de 5 estrelas Interessante
Avaliado na Itália em 1 de janeiro de 2020
Molto interessante ma non aspettatevi un libro semplice :-)
Mr. Truth
5,0 de 5 estrelas It takes more than one read to grasp like any other Jungian work
Avaliado na Índia em 23 de fevereiro de 2018
Phew. It takes more than one read to grasp like any other Jungian work.
3 pessoas acharam isso útil
Denunciar
Ricardo
5,0 de 5 estrelas An excellent book that stimulates the reflection and impels us to go further to understand the nature of reality
Avaliado no México em 4 de março de 2016
Synchronicity is a very interesting book, a Jung's essay containing such a diverse phenomena like ESP, psychokinesis telepathy and astrological experiments, along with scientific, philosophical an epistemological reflections. Jung introduced the idea of synchronicity to strip off the fantasy, the magic, and the superstition related to the unpredictable events that seem to be connected.

Jung states that the current philosophical principle that underlies our conception of natural law is the CAUSALITY. This misunderstanding is caused by several assumptions that rest on the current EPISTEMOLOGY. But, What about the events that have no causal relationship?

"Causality occupies this paramount position with us, but it acquired its importance only in the course of the last two centuries, thanks to the levelling influence of the statistical method on the one hand and the unparalleled success of the natural sciences on the other, which brought the metaphysical view of the world into disrepute."

Jung proposes SYNCHRONICITY as a new factor to explain the reality using a new model that includes both the causal and acausal phenomena. Synchronicity means the simultaneous occurrence of a certain psychic state with one or more external events which appear as meaningful parallels to the momentary subjective state— and, in certain cases, vice versa. An unexpected content which is directly or indirectly connected with some objective external event coincides with the ordinary psychic state.

Jung tries to support his assertions by using statistics and probability to explain acausal phenomena. However synchronicity is a highly abstract and “irrepresentable” quantity. Jung also mentions the work of J. B. Rhine at Duke University and several others on extra-sensory perception (ESP). The probability results of many ESP and telepathic experiments are in the order of 1:millions. This events cannot be explained only with a causal relationship.

Jung introduces some concepts from Schopenhauer, Leibniz, Kant and the Tao in relation with synchronicity. Synchronicity postulates a meaning which is “a priori” in relation to human consciousness and apparently exists outside man.

Synchronicity is a Jung's attempt to unify the scientifically objective world with the subjective psychical world. It is an attemp to scientifically explain the unexplainable, even though the scientific method fails to explain the reality that goes beyond the physical observable and measurable world.

An excellent book that stimulates the reflection and impels us to go further to understand the nature of reality. “Unity and Multiplicity at once”.
7 pessoas acharam isso útil
Denunciar
Stuart Crawford
5,0 de 5 estrelas Five Stars
Avaliado no Reino Unido em 26 de fevereiro de 2015
fantastic brilliant amazing superb good